Plato’s doctrine of the forms
remains one of the most profound worldviews ever attained and created. Its
practical acceptance has admittedly been small, however its grandeur and
intellectual attraction has caused it to live on in the hearts if not minds of
philosophers for centuries. Eventually, it fell to the iron grip of organized
religion, translated by St. Augustine into a religious doctrine[1],
and was thus stripped of its natural beauty and philosophical achievement.
The theory was born out of
various philosophical difficulties which have been the cause of great
controversy ever since. The most notable of difficulties influential and
fundamental to the theory is known as the problem of universals. Universals are
concepts that reflect not a specific object but an underlying universal
prototype that has instances of particular expressions of it. For example, the
concept man refers to no specific object but to a prototype which is reflected
through all men. In a sense, all men are not man itself, but partake in the
concept man. The problem with such phenomena is that the concept is valid
despite its abstractness and lack of physical expression, which indicates the
inadequacy of the physical universe alone to account for conceptual reality.
Physical objects seem to be based on prototypes that are real and recognizable,
existing on their own, and they seem to form and rationalize all of reality. In
subsequent generations this would mostly be considered a psychological
difficulty; however, to Plato our minds reflect absolute truth and objective
rationality and so psychological explanations are necessarily inadequate[2].
Plato thus acknowledged that
universals are actually real, existing as pure ideas, and that all of physical
reality is expressions and instances of these ideas. A dual world was thus
created and defined; the world of ideas, pure and eternal, and the world of
physical expressions and instances of these ideas, ever-changing and mortal. The
eyes are the sense for the physical reality, while the mind or intellectual
soul is the sense with which we grasp intellectual reality[3].
Interestingly, Plato used this
theory to refute Parmenides’s argument which philosophers had grappled with for
years. Parmenides’s argument raises the following difficulty: to speak of
something not in existence is senseless as there is nothing which is referred
to. Thus, to speak of change, which includes speaking about that which went out
of existence, is senseless. As such the concept change is meaningless and is
invalid. Put short, the argument demonstrates that one cannot have a concept of
nothingness, for there is nothing which it refers to, therefore all talk of
nothingness is necessarily senseless. Plato replied based on his theory, that
nothingness is indeed nothing in the physical universe, but remains an idea,
which has existence and meaning forever beyond the physical universe[4].
Naturally, Plato occupied himself
with discovering and perceiving the ultimate and eternal reality, the world of
ideas. One of Plato’s important conclusions was that the idea of goodness is
the light through which all other ideas are discernible. However, it remains
unclear why he thought so. Perhaps his reasoning was as follows. All human
knowledge is only understood subjectively, after all, the very act of understanding
is subjective and personal. Also, one only understands for one’s particular purposes
in that moment, consequentially, one is further prejudiced towards it.
Therefore, we cannot properly access objective knowledge. Our personal minds
are unable and unwilling to reach out objectively to grasp pure objectivity not
having any personal meaning assigned to it. Therefore, it is only through the
idea of goodness, which forms all values, and hence all meaning[5],
that we can properly access objective knowledge. Through our subjective value
assigned to it we can grasp it as subjective and personal knowledge. Indeed, it
is the light which enables us to interpret and discern all other ideas.
We must ask ourselves, why do we
so easily dismiss Plato’s proposition as philosophical fantasy? Generally
people believe their sensory input reflects an objective reality, despite the
fact that all arguments for this belief are circular and no one has yet devised
a sound argument demonstrating this. However, as this is accepted by virtually
everyone, it seems inconsistent that the existence of the world of ideas is
generally unaccepted. After all, in both cases we have information concerning
objective reality that suddenly appears to us, why decide the visual
information and perception reflects objective reality any less than ideological
information and perception does? Ideas, too, are perceived by us as
representing absolute truth and objective credulity, and so should be accepted
as real and objective things.
Furthermore, modern quantum
mechanics seems to provide adequate evidence for the truth of the doctrine of
the forms. Quantum mechanics seems to indicate that the universe without an
observer potentially exists as every possibility, but actually exists as none,
until one observes. These terms however, of potential existence and the
existence of numerous possibilities, cannot be understood as physical
phenomena. Various theories have been introduced to explain this bizarre
finding, each one more surprising and ludicrous than the next. Yet this seems
to be quite obviously a demonstration of the existence of ideas; every
possibility simultaneously exists as ideas. Through these ideas, a world of
actual objects is continuously formed, and so whenever we observe we see a
world of actual phenomena, but when we don’t observe we can recognize that in
reality, the ‘real object’ is the idea of that object, not the object itself,
and so exists in a set of infinite possibility. Somewhat randomly, different
ideas are chosen to form changes in reality.
But we need not rest on the
mysterious and obscure findings of quantum mechanics to gain modern support to
this ancient view. In fact, the entire science demonstrates its truth. Science
is founded on the assumption of natural law, a concept which requires
explanation, and without the existence of forms is utterly senseless. What are,
after all, the laws of nature? It seems this concept arose out of Christian
scientists, specifically deists, who regarded the world as created and
controlled by the dictations of God. However, this picture fails to explain and
account for the laws, for it leaves open the question: how do God’s laws and
desires affect the nature of reality? The most obvious explanation of contingent
law’s and properties which control reality is that these laws aren’t actually
laws but ideas, which the physical universe, being an expression of these
ideas, abides to.
We live in a world which seems to
be surrounded and defined by ideas. Mathematics, for example, defies
explanation and philosophers have long wondered what exactly numbers, and all
mathematical truths and principles, are. Yet again, the most obvious
explanation is that these are ideas. Particularly, this accounts for the massive
success of mathematics in terms of its explanatory power over physical
phenomenon. This reflects the absolute submission of physical phenomenon to the
ideas. Similarly, logical truths can be accounted for as ideas. Morality, as
well, has no place in a world of physical objects and is indication of ideas
existing beyond physical objects, defining and controlling the natural order.
Perhaps ideas are the secret behind aesthetics, as well. A song, for example,
which is a grouping of various tones and chords, somehow when put together in
the ‘correct’ ways, sounds symmetrical and beautiful in a way that is forever
beyond our psychological selves. We recognize good music to be on-tune and can
even discern rules which define what constitutes as musical. These rules,
utterly out of place in a physical universe, can best be described as ideas;
music is an instantiation of ideas.
Perhaps there is no physical
universe, but it itself is an idea composed of ideas. After all, isn’t our
perception of the physical universe itself nothing more than a very grand and
detailed idea? Why don’t we naturally assume, then, that ideas are real, and
the physical universe is but one of the mysterious ideas?
With the modern age came at last
the advent of Atheism and the possibility for new sophisticated worldviews. The
new god of the atheists is materialism, and they have caused much of the
religious and spiritual psychic, fundamental to humans for centuries, to die
out. However, let us not forget that we live in a mysterious world, and our
eyes are only one sense. The most important sense is, of course, the mind,
which discerns logical credulity, and analyzes and accounts for physical
sensory information. When we use the mind to explain reality we are faced with
a very different picture of reality; we see a very spiritual and intellectual
one. Let us not forget about the most important sense of the body, and let us
not forget that as much as science has shown us, the universe is prepared to
show us much more, if we would only apply ourselves with an open mind and not
be blinded by the baseless assumptions of science or religion.
[1]
St. Augustine preached that these ideas are God’s ideas and prototypes for the
world. He thus maintained that through philosophical investigation one can
enter God’s mind and perceive His underlying ideas of the world, a belief which
has helped philosophy gain popularity in the Western Christian world.
[2]
Similarly, Plato struggled to comprehend how one can make a mistake, for it
seems impossible to understand something irrational, as such if one thinks s/he
understands, s/he must actually understand. Again, today this is mostly
understood as a psychological question, to Plato this is a philosophical one
questioning the nature of rationality and the law of the excluded middle.
Another example is Plato’s
conviction that if one understands properly why the good is good, he will
necessarily choose the good, for everyone wants that which is best, and the
good describes that which is best. Reality seems to disagree with Plato on
this; Plato recognized this and was forced to explain the reality in a somewhat
desperate and unlikely way because of his a priori reasoning. Here yet again, most
would consider this a psychological phenomenon, but to Plato the mind is
necessarily rational and objective.
It’s worth noting that
Aristotle, who was amongst the founders of modern psychology, disagreed with
Plato on this, and also disagreed on Plato’s insistence on the objectiveness of
ideas.
[3]
Plato himself didn’t view it this way; he thought one is born with all ideas
already in place. He argued that otherwise one can’t be convinced of truth, for
how does one know if something is true unless he has the information deep
inside him already. For various reasons this was not included in the text.
[4] I
have been bothered by a similar question to Parmenides’s argument, but one that
I feel is more difficult to answer: how could there be truths about states of
absolute nothingness, there is nothing to have truths about? Yet there
certainly are such truths, such as the truth that it is indeed a state of
nothingness. Possibly, an idea of nothingness explains why there are truths
about it. Indeed, without the idea of nothingness as well, there would be no
truths, but of course we don’t understand this for we have never imagined a
true state of nothingness, for that is impossible, as Parmenides demonstrated.
[5]
Although some philosophers would disapprove of such grouping, Plato would not
be among them. He understood goodness as personal and profitable, as seen
through his argument that if one understands properly the good he will
doubtlessly do the good, as quoted in the previous footnote.
No comments:
Post a Comment